Left Menu
Life News
Are we using our memory for the glory of God? by Timothy Raymond
Can we in good conscience vote for Labor? by Andrew Lansdown and Dwight A. Randall
National MP slams perversity of Safe Schools program
Adult children of gay parents testify against same-sex marriage by Kirsten Andersen
Domestic Violence: Women can be as abusive as men by Dr Augusto Zimmerman
With the Lord: Wilma Drew
18th Annual Walk and Rally for Life
Former senator speaks up for the unborn by Joe Bullock
Qurans deadly role in inspiring Belgian slaughter by Nabeel Qureshi
Germany:Christian refugees persecuted by Muslims by Soeren Kern
Web Design and Development - abcplus Publishing Australia
Pamphlets
by Andrew Lansdown
One for All
A Son to the war
Becoming a Christian
Train home
Sons Laid Down Their Lives
An Accurate Diagnosis
Starting again
Following hard after God
Starving our children
The first duty of fatherhood
The origin of fatherhood
An Easter Song
A Christmas carol
For This Purpose
In royal David's city
God's Placard
Believing the Bible: the issue of inerrancy
Marriage according to scripture
A biblical perspective on prostitution
Prostitution and social justice
Abortion: A biblical perspective
If people were dogs & other false arguments for euthanasia
How porn harms us
How Green is God?
Evolution?
Christians and Politics
When Christians Take Their Lives
The High Kings Watchmen

No-fault divorce and the moral basis for spousal support

 

No-fault divorce and the moral basis for spousal support

by Augusto Zimmermann

During the period when the law still regarded marriage as the union between husband and wife to be indissoluble except by death, a wife had a life-long right to be supported by her husband (unless that right was forfeited by her own actions).

Back in those days marriage was considered an institution with effective contractual overtones, which provided the wronged party with the right to seek compensation and to be released from the marriage relationship.

Under this “fault” system, compensation was available on grounds of matrimonial offence relating to adultery, cruelty and desertion. The courts were then required to consider the commission of offence, and the party responsible for the marital breakdown would be held accountable for his misbehaviour.

In this context, any award of financial support reflected not only an element of assistance to the spouse unable to support herself, but also an element of punishment of the “guilty” party. As such, if a man deserted his wife she could successfully apply for the right of financial support.

Hence, in the 1964 case of Davis v Davis, Justice (Sir) John Barry of the Victorian Supreme Court declared: “The broad notion acceptable to the community is, I think, that if a husband of means irretrievably destroys the reality of a marriage, and it appears that he contemplates marriage with another woman whom he prefers to his wife, the court should ensure that he pays to the spouse he is repudiating whatever, having regard to his means and his conduct towards her, and her conduct towards him, is fair and reasonable, recognising that he is pursuing his own gratification in disregard of obligations he undertook.”1

In a subsequent decision in Atkinson v Atkinson (1969), Barry stated: “The conduct of a husband amounting to a matrimonial offence is considered … a necessary element in determining what order is proper … or what order is just and equitable in the circumstances of the case.”2

By contrast, a wife who committed adultery forfeited her right to spousal maintenance absolutely. In Adams v Adams (1968), the Supreme Court of New South Wales, under Justice Colin Begg, said of the woman who violated the marriage vow: “In the usual case a wife who has been found guilty of a matrimonial offence will not be awarded maintenance.”3

Before the introduction in 1975 of “no-fault” divorce, therefore, spousal support rested on the premise that the party who was not legally at fault for the marital breakdown was entitled to a form of expectation damages.4

The idea relied on the indissolubility of marriage, which for the husband involved a continuing obligation to support his wife. That being so, a man who had broken the promise of supporting a woman by entering into matrimony still had the legal obligation to look after her welfare if she was in need and unable to support herself.5

During the “no-fault” revolution in Western societies throughout the 1960s and 1970s, the law removed considerations of “fault” and divorce became a “right” freely available at the decision of one spouse even against the wishes of the other. As such, “need” replaced “fault” as the primary criterion for awarding spousal support.

There are, however, significant difficulties in justifying support in jurisdictions that have removed the fault-based aspects of spousal maintenance. Naturally, it is not so difficult to justify support for a wife who is abandoned for a younger woman or for a wife who leaves her husband because of his violence.

However, it is much more difficult to justify support for a wife who decides to leave for reasons such as boredom or because she has formed a new relationship outside the marital relationship.6

To the extent that she is unable to support herself independently, a disloyal wife still remains legally entitled to receive support from her betrayed husband.

The apparent anomaly is consistent with the feminist approach to heterosexual marriage. Radical feminists regard marriage as a “patriarchal” institution based on gender inequality and the division of labour between men and women. In this context, instead of perpetuating women’s dependency, spousal support is viewed as a compensation to be expected and earned for every wife who divorces her male “oppressor”.

According to such feminist scholars, feminism supports law which not only “recognises and rejects the categories of public and private”, but which “must also reject traditional categories of … husband and wife”.7

Although acknowledging the variety of reasons why a marriage might break down, it is not unreasonable to question the legitimacy of a system which compels someone to support an unfaithful spouse who leaves the relationship for entirely unilateral and selfish motivations.

It should be a valid defence to any claim for support that the party seeking compensation was in some way directly responsible for the end of the marital relationship.8

For these reasons, in the rationale for spousal maintenance some recognition of responsibility for the marital breakdown should be taken into full consideration.9

In the past, the law has been criticised for conscious or unconscious gender biases in its operation. This may well be so, but now we are witnessing a more distinctive contribution by feminist ideology: the conscious reward of selfish behaviour and the deliberate undermining of justice by family law.

Endnotes

1. Davis v Davis [1964] VR 278 at 282.
2. Davis v Davis [1964] VR 278 at 281.
3. Adams v Adams (1968) 11 FLR 197 at 200.
4. Patrick Parkinson, Family Law and the Indissolubility of Parenthood (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2011), p.249.
5. Ibid., p.250.
6. Ibid., p.249.
7. Alison Diduck and Helena Orton, “Equality and support for spouses” (1994)57 The Modern Law Review 681, 687.
8. Parkinson, op. cit., p.258.
9. Ibid., p.257.
 
Augusto Zimmermann, LLB, LLM, PhD (Monash), is a Senior Lecturer in Law at Murdoch University. He is also a Commissioner with the Law Reform Commission of WA; Fellow at the International Academy for the Study of the Jurisprudence of the Family (IASJF); President of the Western Australian Legal Theory Association (WALTA); and Editor of The Western Australian Jurist. Last year he published a widely acclaimed book, Western Legal Theory: Theory, Concepts and Perspectives (Sydney: LexisNexis Butterworths, 2013).
 
This article was first published in News Weekly and is reprinted in Life News by kind permission of the author.
Web Design and Development - abcplus Publishing Australia
Web Design and Development - abcplus Publishing Australia
LIFE NEWS ARCHIVES
2015 Vol 3 Jul - Sep
2015 Vol 2 Apr - Jun
2015 Vol 1 Jan - Mar
2014 Vol 5 Nov - Dec
2014 Vol 4 Sep - Oct
2014 Vol 3 Jun - Aug
2014 Vol 2 Apr - May
2014 Vol 1 Feb - Mar
2013 Vol 5 Dec - Jan
2013 Vol 4 Sep - Nov
2013 Vol 3 Jun - Aug
2013 Vol 2 Apr - May
2013 Vol 1 Jan - Mar
2012 Vol 5 Oct - Dec
2012 Vol 4 Aug - Sep
2012 Vol 3 May - Jul
2012 Vol 2 Mar - Apr
2012 Vol 1 Jan - Feb
2011 Vol 3 Jun - Aug
2011 Vol 2 Apr - May
2011 Vol 1 Jan - Mar
2010 Vol 5 Nov - Dec
2010 Vol 4 Sep - Oct
2010 Vol 3 Jun - Aug
2010 Vol 2 Sep - Oct
2010 Vol 2 Apr - May
2010 Vol 1 Jan - Mar
2009 Vol 4 Aug - Sep
2009 Vol 3 Jun - Jul
2009 Vol 2 Apr - May
2009 Vol 1 Feb - Mar
2008 Vol 5 Oct - Dec
2008 Vol 4 Aug - Sep
2008 Vol 3 Jun - July
2008 Vol 2 Apr - May
2008 Vol 1 Feb - Mar
2007 Vol 5 Nov - Jan
2007 Vol 4 Aug - Oct
2007 Vol 3 Jun - Jul
2007 Vol 2 Apr - May
2007 Vol 1 Feb - Mar
2006 Vol 5 Oct - Nov
2006 Vol 4 Aug - Sep
2006 Vol 3 Jun - Jul
2006 Vol 2 Apr - May
2006 Vol 1 Feb - Mar
2005 Vol 6 Dec - Jan
2005 Vol 5 Oct - Nov
2005 Vol 4 Aug - Sep
2005 Vol 3 Jun - Jul
2005 Vol 2 Apr - May
2005 Vol 1 Feb - Mar